IDEAS home Printed from https://ideas.repec.org/a/bpj/jeehcn/v14y2004i2n4.html
   My bibliography  Save this article

The Market as an Environment

Author

Listed:
  • Viskovatoff Alex

    (University of Pittsburgh)

Abstract

More than perhaps any other major social theorist, Niklas Luhmann adopted a perspective on society at the opposite end of the atomistic-holistic spectrum to that of mainstream economics. While the position of mainstream economics is that society is nothing more than a collection of individuals, so that it can be understood simply in terms of those individuals and their interactions, Luhmann abstracts from individuals entirely, understanding social phenomena as being produced by society itself, with individuals playing a merely peripheral or "enabling" role. This radical reconceptualization of society and the relation of the individual to society allowed Luhmann to build from the ground up a highly systematic theory of society which allows one to formulate economic and social questions in new ways, freed from preconceptions that are poorly grounded or simply wrong. After providing a brief overview of Luhmann's general social theory, this article considers two questions for which Luhmann's theory can produce a fresh point of view. The first concerns what is the nature of markets. According to Luhmann, markets are not a kind of system (the common if tacit view), but collections of observations--the observations of market participants of other market participants. The second concerns the old question of what is the appropriate degree of intervention in the economy. Mainstream economics approaches this problem through the distinction between (free) markets and planning. According to Luhmann, this is a false dichotomy, since all economies have markets and planning. The real question is who should do the planning: private organizations or the state. The former operate on the basis of competition, that is, rivalry; the latter operates on the basis of cooperation. The problem with "socialist" or "centrally planned" economies was not that they were planned or centrally organized, since "free market" economies have planning and centralization too; it was that they relied solely on cooperation, with there being no space for competition. The paper concludes with some reflections on whether freemarket economies with minimal intervention by the state are any more sustainable than are "socialist" economies.Niklas Luhmann, peut-être plus que les autres auteurs en théorie sociale, a adopté une approche de la société qui est à l'opposé du spectre individualismeholisme des économistes orthodoxes. Alors que l'économie orthodoxe considère que la société n'est rien d'autre que la somme des individus et qu'elle ne peut être appréhendée qu'en termes d'individus et de leurs interactions, Luhmann fait totalement abstraction des individus et comprend les phénomènes sociaux comme étant produits par la société elle-même dans laquelle les individus jouent un rôle périphérique ou un rôle "d'habilitation". Cette radicale reconceptualization de la société ainsi que la relation des individus à la société a permis à Luhmann de construire une théorie très méthodique de la société qui permet d'appréhender de façon différente les questions économiques et sociales, sans préreprésentations fragiles ou erronées. Après avoir donné un aperçu général de la théorie sociale de Luhmann, l'article considère deux questions pour lesquelles la théorie de Luhmann peut apporter un nouveau point de vue. La première traite de la nature des marchés. D'après Luhmann, les marchés ne sont pas une sorte de système (comme cela est souvent considéré) mais des sommes d'observations faites par les participants au marché sur les autres participants. La seconde question concerne l'éternel problème du degré d'interventionnisme dans l'économie. Les économistes orthodoxes abordent cette question à travers la distinction entre les marchés (libres) et la planification. D'après Luhmann cette dichotomie est erronée dans la mesure où toutes les économies connaissent à la fois le marché et la planification. La véritable question est: Qui devrait planifier: les organisations privées ou l'Etat?. Les premières agissent sur la base de la concurrence, i.e de la rivalité; l'Etat agit sur la base de la coopération. Le problème avec les économies "socialistes" ou "centralement planifiées" n'est pas qu'elles sont planifiées ou qu'elles relèvent d'une organisation centralisée puisque les économies de "marché libre" connaissent aussi la planification et la centralisation. Le problème vient du fait qu'elles reposent uniquement sur la coopération et n'accordent pas de place à la concurrence. Le papier conclut en s'interrogeant sur l'idée selon laquelle les économies de libre marché avec une intervention étatique minimale sont plus viables que les économies "socialistes".

Suggested Citation

  • Viskovatoff Alex, 2004. "The Market as an Environment," Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, De Gruyter, vol. 14(2), pages 1-19, December.
  • Handle: RePEc:bpj:jeehcn:v:14:y:2004:i:2:n:4
    DOI: 10.2202/1145-6396.1126
    as

    Download full text from publisher

    File URL: https://doi.org/10.2202/1145-6396.1126
    Download Restriction: For access to full text, subscription to the journal or payment for the individual article is required.

    File URL: https://libkey.io/10.2202/1145-6396.1126?utm_source=ideas
    LibKey link: if access is restricted and if your library uses this service, LibKey will redirect you to where you can use your library subscription to access this item
    ---><---

    As the access to this document is restricted, you may want to search for a different version of it.

    References listed on IDEAS

    as
    1. Alex Viskovatoff, 2003. "Searle, Rationality, and Social Reality," American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Wiley Blackwell, vol. 62(1), pages 7-44, January.
    2. Alex Viskovatoff, 2003. "Rationalism and mainstream economics," Journal of Economic Methodology, Taylor & Francis Journals, vol. 10(3), pages 397-415.
    Full references (including those not matched with items on IDEAS)

    Most related items

    These are the items that most often cite the same works as this one and are cited by the same works as this one.
    1. Alan Hamlin, 2014. "Reasoning about rules," Constitutional Political Economy, Springer, vol. 25(1), pages 68-87, March.
    2. Pietro Guarnieri, 2017. "Commitment to norms and the formation of institutions," Discussion Papers 2017/227, Dipartimento di Economia e Management (DEM), University of Pisa, Pisa, Italy.

    Corrections

    All material on this site has been provided by the respective publishers and authors. You can help correct errors and omissions. When requesting a correction, please mention this item's handle: RePEc:bpj:jeehcn:v:14:y:2004:i:2:n:4. See general information about how to correct material in RePEc.

    If you have authored this item and are not yet registered with RePEc, we encourage you to do it here. This allows to link your profile to this item. It also allows you to accept potential citations to this item that we are uncertain about.

    If CitEc recognized a bibliographic reference but did not link an item in RePEc to it, you can help with this form .

    If you know of missing items citing this one, you can help us creating those links by adding the relevant references in the same way as above, for each refering item. If you are a registered author of this item, you may also want to check the "citations" tab in your RePEc Author Service profile, as there may be some citations waiting for confirmation.

    For technical questions regarding this item, or to correct its authors, title, abstract, bibliographic or download information, contact: Peter Golla (email available below). General contact details of provider: https://www.degruyter.com .

    Please note that corrections may take a couple of weeks to filter through the various RePEc services.

    IDEAS is a RePEc service. RePEc uses bibliographic data supplied by the respective publishers.